Gabriel Marcel on Creativity and Hope

There are two ideas in Marcel’s philosophy, in addition to those discussed in yesterday’s post, that I would like to discuss briefly—the importance of creative fidelity and of hope.

Creative Fidelity – For Marcel to exist existentially, as opposed to just functionally, one must be creative. As he argues: “A really alive person is not merely someone who has a taste for life, but somebody who spreads that taste, showering it, as it were, around him; and a person who is really alive in this way has, quite apart from any tangible achievements of [theirs], something essentially creative about [them] …”1

What Marcel calls “creative fidelity” involves giving a part of ourselves to others, which we do by sharing love and friendship, as well as through the creative, performing, and fine arts. Creative fidelity binds us to others, recognizing their subjectivity while expressing our own. Creative fidelity is the tenacious, constant desire to elaborate who we are—to have a greater sense of being, we need creative fidelity. We become creatively faithful when we bridge the gap between ourselves and others, when we make ourselves present  to them. 

Hope – Hope guarantees fidelity by defeating despair—it gives us the strength to continually create—but it is not the same as optimism. Optimism, like fear or desire, imagines or anticipates a favorable or unfavorable outcome. We “desire that x” or “fear that x.” Hope is different. We don’t hope that x, we simply hope. Hope rejects the current situation as final, but it doesn’t anticipate a specific result that will deliver us from our plight, it transcends anticipating a specific form of our deliverance—it is a vague hoping. My desires can be thwarted, but if I maintain hope no outcome will shake me from my hope. (It seems I could say the same the same of my desires or fears.) It is the very non-specificity of hoping, according to Marcel, that gives hope its power.

Yet hope is not passive; it is not resignation or acceptance. Instead “Hope consists in asserting that there is at the heart of being, beyond all data, beyond all inventories and all calculations, a mysterious principle which is in connivance with me.”2 And hope is a willing, a wanting, not only for ourselves but for others. “There can be no hope that does not constitute itself through a we and for a we. I would be tempted to say that all hope is at the bottom choral.”3 For genuine hope we cannot depend completely upon ourselves—it derives from humility not pride.

Thus there is a dialectical relationship between hope and despair. We can respond to despair with hope, and within hope there is always the possibility of despair. To despair is to say there is nothing worthwhile in the world: “Despair is possible in any form, at any moment and to any degree, and this betrayal may seem to be counseled, if not forced upon us, by the very structure of the world we live in.”4 Hope is an affirmative response to despair. Hope affirms that your creative fidelity, your work, your concern, your love, and your life, all ultimately matter.

Reflections – I like the idea of creative fidelity. It is reminiscent of Marx’s idea of non-alienated labor, labor that elaborates who we are, connecting us with ourselves, nature and others. The world would be better if culture encouraged us to be creatively faithful.

I also like the idea of hope, but I think the distinction between optimism, hope, wishes, and longings needs to be more carefully drawn. The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language defines optimism as: “A tendency to expect the best possible outcome or dwell on the most hopeful aspects of a situation.” In neither of these senses am I or is Marcel an optimist. We do not expect our most fervent wishes to come true, nor do we dwell on the most hopeful possibilities. The same source defines hope similarly: “To wish for something with expectation of its fulfillment. To look forward to with confidence or expectation.” In neither of these senses do I or Marcel have hope, because hope thus defined anticipates or expects an outcome.

The sense of hope that both Marcel and I believe in is the verb form of hope—hoping that something happens or becomes the case—which is essentially the same as wishing or longing for something. We hope, wish, or long for some vaguely defined outcome which we do not expect to be fulfilled. For example, we may wish or hope that life is meaningful. But to wish or hope this does not imply that we believe, have faith in, anticipate, or expect that life is meaningful—we are just hoping. Furthermore, our wishes, hopes and longings exist in the realm of emotions, and are thereby immune from intellectual criticism. After all there is nothing irrational about hoping we win a lottery. We may know the chances of winning are remote, but as long as it’s possible to win, there is nothing wrong with wishing that we win. Of course it’s stupid to think that we’ll win a typical lottery, or to plan our life as if we’ll win, but surely it is permissible to wish or hope for the winning numbers.

Finally, I will say this about hope, and I think Marcel would agree. Hope helps us to brave the struggle of life, while keeping alive the possibility that we will create a better and more meaningful reality. Hope is most precious. Yes, Kazantzakis thought hope was the final temptation to be overcome for a life to be genuine, but he was wrong. There is nothing intellectually or morally dishonest about about hoping things turn out for the best.

__________________________________________________________________________

1. Marcel, Gabriel. The Mystery of Being, Volume I.  (Chicago: Charles Regnery Co, 1951) 139.
2. The Philosophy of Existentialism. Translated by Manya Harari. New York: Carol Publishing Group, 1995) 28.
3. Tragic Wisdom and Beyond. Translated by Stephen Jolin and Peter McCormick. Publication of the Northwestern University Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy, ed. John Wild. (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973) 143.
4. The Philosophy of Existentialism. Translated by Manya Harari. New York: Carol Publishing Group, 1995) 26.

2 thoughts on “Gabriel Marcel on Creativity and Hope

  1. I found this article particularly interesting in regards to the relationship between hope and creativity which you and Marcel lay out. I agree with the descriptions of the creative and hopeful processes which highlight their interdependent relationship. In terms of our creativity, Marcel’s assertion that our creativity should be “spread” or “showered” on those around us solicits a sort of hope that there exists something greater than the solitary self. In conjunction with the Kantian idea that we cannot confirm the existence of any metaphysical phenomena, humanity’s sole connection to this external force/existence would be the hope that it is there to be interacted with. In addition, Marcel’s accounts of hope as essential to the creative process, his descriptions of the process of hope itself seems creative in its own right. He states that hope is dynamic in contrast to the the static and unchanging nature of stoicism. For me, this brings to mind a creativity and openness to change which would definitely serve one well in the practice of hope. In this sense, the qualities of openness and malleability seem to be necessary for both creativity as well as hope.
    Your distinction between the dictionary definition of hope and the process of hope which Marcel and you identify with highlights this openness and dynamic quality of hopefulness. It combines the humility of stoicism with an unassuming receptiveness reminiscent of Eastern philosophies. However your previous post on Kazantzakis’ “rejection of hope” seems to dispute the definition of hope itself. Kazantzakis’ perception of hope aligns more so with the definition which you give here of optimism, in which there exists some level of expectation for the favorable and some level of fear that the unfavorable will come to pass. Kazantzakis’ statement that most noble cause a person can commit themselves to is the search for meaning and substance in life interestingly parallels Marcel’s idea of an active sort of hope. The two philosophers in the end seem to emphasize the dynamic lifestyle and search for significance over the passive and assuming one.

  2. Thoughtful comments. I’ll have to think more about whether Kazantzakis’ rejection of hope is really a rejection of optimism. Kazantzakis’ rejection of hope has always affected me, as I’m a great admirer of his thinking. And you are correct, they are both searchers for meaning. Perhaps searching itself manifests hope. Perhaps Kazantzakis had hope after all. Thanks for the insights.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *